Let's throw some big words onto the table:
speculative realism, object-oriented philosophy, the digital humanities, and
conceptualist poetics. They all
belong there together, I think, because they all have something to do with one
possible future for literary studies.
Graham Harman is the leading figure of the movement known in philosophy
as speculative realism or object-oriented philosophy. While his name seems to strike fear into the hearts of the
more uptight members of the Anglo-American philosophical community, he remains
relatively unknown among those concerned with literary study, even in those
circles where philosophically-informed critical theory holds sway. All that may change, though: in the
past few years he seems to have become more focused on the interdisciplinary
possibilities of his thinking, and he's begun to speculate about just what his
brand of thinking could mean for the future of literary study. It's a weird prospect he presents, but
an intriguing one. What is more,
it's a future that could easily build on two growing developments in thinking
about literature: digital humanistic study of the sort practiced by Franco
Moretti at Stanford's Literary Lab; and conceptualist poetics as practiced most
prominently by Kenneth Goldsmith.
Speculative
Realism
Harman tells us that speculative realism is
"weird realism" (he likes the phrase so much it appears as part of
the title of his book Weird Realism: Lovecraft and Philosophy). While we literary types might want to
think of "realism" as a nineteenth century literary movement, Harman
uses it in a sense specific to philosophy: as one term in the realist/idealist
debate. Realists, in this context,
are those who believe in an objective, exterior world of things-in-themselves,
existing independently of our minds; while idealists like Kant believe that the only world we can know is the world of things present to our mind, the
world of mental phenomena. In the
long history of realists vs. idealists, realists have tended to be the
commonsensical bunch, those who seem least weird and most down to earth. One thinks of Boswell's anecdote about
Samuel Johnson responding to Berkeley's idealist speculations, in which the
rebuttal to idealism could not have been more concrete:
After we came out of the church, we stood talking
for some time together of Bishop Berkeley's ingenious sophistry to prove the
nonexistence of matter, and that every thing in the universe is merely ideal. I
observed, that though we are satisfied his doctrine is not true, it is
impossible to refute it. I never shall forget the alacrity with which Johnson
answered, striking his foot with mighty force against a large stone, till he rebounded
from it -- "I refute it thus."
Vulgar empiricism! It worked for Johnson, but for
Harman it just won't do. He comes
by his realism from another source: Heidegger, specifically the tool theory
sections of Being and Time.
Most of us in literary studies who cut our teeth on
continental literary theory have absorbed, to one degree or another, the sense
of reality as socially constructed, as the product of discourse or language, or
as constituted in social systems of one sort or another. Whether our maître à penser was
Foucault, Derrida, Deleuze, Bourdieu, or, if we're very hip indeed, Bruno
Latour, we've tended to believe in objects as formed by human consciousness or consciousness' products (such as language or systems of prestige). Harman believes, instead, that objects
necessarily exceed their relationship to humanity, and even their relationship
to each other. As he put it in an
interview for the Cultural Technologies podcast, his theory centers on "the
notion that the objects of the world are not exhausted by their interactions,
that there is some nucleus in the object that is never fully deployed in its
relations." This grew out of
Heidegger, especially those parts of Heidegger's thinking that rebel against
the phenomenological philosophy of his mentor Husserl, who was interested in
the way objects appear in human consciousness. For Husserl, objects were important in terms of their
appearance to us, but Heidegger saw that things exist, for the most part, without
our consciousness. We depend on
them as tools or equipment, but even as we're doing this they're not something
we think about, or are conscious of.
Things, for Heidegger, are mostly not in our consciousness, but are
unconsciously relied on and taken for granted. Things don't tend to appear in consciousness until something
goes wrong with them: you don't think about your computer keyboard until the
space bar sticks; you don't think about the hammer you're using until it breaks
(the latter is Heidegger's famous example in Being and Time—you might recall
something similar being said about shoes his "Origin of the Work of
Art").
Harman goes a step further than Heidegger: for him,
it's not just that objects go deeper than our consciousness because of being
used without being present in the mind: the object goes deeper even than its
use. The existence of the hammer
exceeds both consciousness and use, and withdraws from us in ways upon which we
can only speculate. It can't be
summed up by how we think about it or use it. Neither can it be explained as a bundle of its
components. As Harman puts it,
Just as humans do not dissolve into their parents
or children but rather have a certain autonomy from both, so too a rock is
neither downwardly reducible to quarks and electrons nor upwardly reducible to
its role in stoning the Interior Ministry. The rock has rock properties not found in its tiny
components, and also has rock properties not exhausted by its uses. The rock is not affected when a few of
its protons are destroyed by cosmic rays, and by the same token it is never
exhaustively deployed in its current use or in all its possible uses. The rock does not exist because it can
be used, but can be used because it exists…. It is a real form outside our minds. It is what medieval philosophers called
a substantial form: the reality of an individual object over and above its
matter, and under and beneath its apprehension by the mind.
One might say that Harman's philosophy is concerned
with essences, in that it is looking for what makes a thing itself, in excess
of its uses or relations or components.
"The term 'essence' gets a bad press these days," Harmon once
told an interviewer for Design and Culture, "because it has come to be
associated with all kinds of repressive and reactionary dogmas, but if we take
'essence' in a more minimalistic sense to mean 'what a thing is quite apart
from its accidental circumstances,' then a certain essentialism is
unavoidable." Moreover, we're
not going to get access to those essences, or even look for them. We're going to "look instead at
how individual entities… withdraw" from systems of definition or use or
relation.
Essentialism
and Weird Realism
Maybe the point about essentialism and its putative
relation to reactionary views is worth elaborating on. Harman certainly does elaborate on
it—here's a passage from his article "The Well-Wrought Broken
Hammer":
According to one familiar narrative… philosophers
used to be naïve realists who believed in real things outside their social or
linguistic contexts; these things were ascribed timeless essences that were not
politically innocent, since they subjugated various groups by pigeonholing each
of them as oriental, feminine, pre-Enlightenment or some other such tag. According to this view, we have luckily
come to realize that essences must be replaced with events and performances,
that the notion of a reality that is not a reality for someone is dubious, that
flux is prior to stasis, that things must be seen as differences rather than
solid units…
The thing about this narrative, though, is that it
takes one view of objects and their essences as the only possible view of them:
The problem with individual substances was never
that they were autonomous or individual, but that they were wrongly conceived
as eternal, unchanging, simple, or directly accessible by certain privileged
observers. By contrast, the
objects of object-oriented philosophy are mortal, ever-changing, built from
swarms of subcomponents, and accessible only through oblique allusion. This is not the oft-lamented 'naïve
realism' of oppressive and benighted patriarchs, but a weird realism in which
real individual objects resist all forms of causal or cognitive mastery.
An emphasis on the question of what makes an object
itself is not, then, a sure sign of reaction: this is not your father's
essentialism.
Object-Oriented
Literary Study
What could all of this have to do with literary
study? Well, for starters, its one
more nail in the coffin of one of the old dogmas of the New Criticism—that
every part of the poem exerts pressure on every other part, and that no part is
extractable without utterly changing the poem's meaning and effect (this is
really a more of a refutation of Cleanth Brooks' "Irony as a Principle of
Structure" than of New Criticism as a whole, which was wider and more
various than most of its current detractors and advocates seems to believe). Here's Harman discussing the famous
ending of Keats' "Ode on a Grecian Urn," with the assertion (the
urn's, not Keats') that "beauty is truth, truth beauty."
If Keats' 'beauty is truth, truth beauty' can only
adequately be read as the outcome of the earlier part of the poem, this is not
true of the whole of the earlier portions, Cleanth Brooks notwithstanding. We can add alternate spellings or even
misspellings to scattered words earlier in the text, without changing the
feeling of the climax. We can
change punctuations slightly, and even change the exact words of a certain
number of lines before 'beauty is truth, truth beauty' begins to take on different
overtones. In short, we cannot
identify the literary work with the exact current form it happens to have.
What is essential to the poem remaining itself is
not immediately clear, but the insistence on total integrity doesn't hold up,
as far as Harman is concerned, no more than the sense that a few protons of an
individual rock being destroyed would destroy its identity as a rock. What we can't do is determine the
essence of the particular literary text: "the literary text," writes
Harman, "runs deeper than any coherent meaning, and outruns the intentions
of the author and reader alike."
What, then, can we do?
Here's where things get interesting—because we can try, through various
methods of indirection, to allude to what makes Keats' ode itself. We won't get to the core of the thing,
but we can begin to understand the nature of what makes that poem that poem,
and we can understand something about what would mark the limits of the poem,
when we would find that it is no longer itself. The critic of a text or set of texts would go about this
sort of thing by
...attempting various modifications of these texts
and seeing what happens. Instead
of just writing about Moby-Dick, why not try shortening it to various degrees
in order to discover the point at which it ceases to sound like Moby-Dick? Why not imagine it lengthened even
further, or told by a third-person narrator rather than by Ishmael, or
involving a cruise in the opposite direction around the globe? Why not consider a scenario under which
Pride and Prejudice were set in upscale Parisian neighborhoods rather than
rural England—could such a text plausibly still be Pride and Prejudice? Why not imagine that a letter by
Shelley was actually written by Nietzsche, and consider the resulting consequences
and lack of consequences? … all the preceding suggestions involve ways of
decontextualizing works… showing that they are to some extent autonomous even
of their own properties. Moby-Dick
differs from its own exact length and its own modifiable plot details, and is a
certain je ne sais quoi or substance able to survive certain modifications and
not others.
It's a different world than what we normally think
of as the province of the literary critic, isn't it? But it's also a world that has to some extent already come
into being, independently of Harman's recommendation.
Goldsmith,
Moretti, and a Future for Literary Study
We've seen decontextualizations very much along the
lines suggested by Harman— but not in the main works of literary critics working
in any of our conventional modes (new historicist, formalist, Marxian,
feminist, poststructuralist, etc.).
We've seen it much more consistently in the works of conceptualist poets
like Kenneth Goldsmith. Consider
Goldsmith's transcription works: his typing, verbatim, of a year's worth of
weather reports in his 2005 book The Weather, or his transcription, again
verbatim, of the September 1, 2000 issue of The New York Times in the 2003 book
Day. These projects raise many
questions (including questions about the meaning of manual transcription in the
age of mechanical reproduction, about the meaning of authorship and the
importance or unimportance of originality, and about whether a poem needs to be
read or simply acknowledged as a concept). But Goldsmith's conceptualist projects also raise exactly
the kind of question Harman raises with " Why not imagine that a letter by
Shelley was actually written by Nietzsche, and consider the resulting
consequences and lack of consequences?" Why not imagine that the September 1, 2000 issue of The New
York Times was a book written by Kenneth Goldsmith? What are the consequences or lack of consequences? Goldsmith has undertaken other projects
very much in accord with other elements of Harman's projected future for literary
studies. Consider, for example,
the following items from his 2002 list poem "Head Citations":
1.
This is the dawning of the age of malaria.
2.
Another one fights the dust.
3.
Eyeing little girls with padded pants.
4.
Teenage spacemen we're all spacemen.
5. A
gay pair of guys put up a parking lot.
5.1.
It tastes very nice, food of the parking lot.
6.
One thing I can tell you is you got to eat cheese.
7.
She was a gay stripper.
8.
Fly like a negro to the sea.
9.
Hey you, get off of my cow.
It is, as you've probably noticed, a list of
misheard musical lyrics. The poem
contains some 800 of them, taken from various sources. The distortion of the original text is
not so great that all of the lyrics are unrecognizable, though we've clearly
moved beyond the words as written by the songwriters. The question of how far is too far, of where the limits of
the song are to be found, comes to the fore—and gets complicated by the fact
that these mishearings are all actual instances of what people have experienced
when they've heard the songs. Once
again, Goldsmith's practice anticipates Harman's call for action—it's
object-oriented literary criticism avant
la lettre.
Goldsmith remains a controversial figure in poetry
circles, and it would take a remarkably progressive English professor to
consider what he does a kind of literary criticism. But what about Franco Moretti? His lit-crit bona
fides are as respectable as one could wish: he's written extensively in the
Marxian mode, holds the appropriate degrees, holds an endowed chair at
Stanford, and has published a half-dozen books of criticism, well received in
many quarters. He's also at the
forefront of the movement for the digital study of the humanities, running
Stanford's Literature Lab. The
massive digitization projects done at Stanford under his direction have yielded
all sorts of interesting results, but one of the directions Moretti has taken
comes tantalizingly close to the project outlined by Harman. The most fascinating part of Moretti's
recent book The Bourgeois examines
what many may think of as an unpromising topic: verb forms in Daniel Defoe's Robinson Crusoe. His analysis of those verb forms leads
him to notice that the most typical formation involves Crusoe narrating events
in a sequence moving from the past participle to the simple past and on to an
infinitive. "Having stowed my
boat," says Crusoe, "I went on to shore," and then concludes
with "to look about me" (I am indebted to David Winters for this
particular example). This is
important, says Moretti, because it embodies the bourgeois worldview of
instrumental reason and deferred gratification: of doing something in order to
prepare for a next step that will lead to another step in an ever-proceeding
process of building and mastering.
It's a far cry from the verbal structures we find in Homeric epic, where
the "Having done that I did that in order to do the new thing"
pattern is in relative abeyance.
Gathering this kind of data is important—but monkeying with it could be
even more important. Moretti has
the technical resources to make massive substitutions: he could change Crusoe's
verb forms around electronically, and produce exactly the kind of modified text
Harman describes, allowing us to investigate the boundary at which Robinson Crusoe ceases to be
recognizably itself. How important
is that bourgeois verbal structure?
One modification would go unnoticed by even the most committed Defoe
expert. When would we meet the
threshold?
One often hears that there's little happening in
literary studies lately, that after the theory wars of the last decades of the
twentieth century we have become complacent, or given up on innovation in
literary criticism. The model
propose by Harman is not as far-fetched as it may seem—in fact, it has already
taken root among creative writers and those most committed to bringing
technology to the study of literature.
We won't know how valuable it could be until we try it in earnest. So I say we work to get Harman, Goldsmith, and Moretti installed on three adjacent bar stools. When they walk out of the joint, they might just be able to point us to where we could be going.